A blog from the Centre for Research Ethics & Bioethics (CRB)

Tag: death

Of course, but: ethics in palliative practice

What is obvious in principle may turn out to be less obvious in practice. That would be at least one possible interpretation of a new study on ethics in palliative care.

Palliative care is given to patients with life-threatening illnesses that cannot be cured. Although palliative care can sometimes contribute to extending life somewhat, the focus is on preventing and alleviating symptoms in the final stages of life. The patient can also receive support to deal with worries about death, as well as guidance on practical issues regarding finances and relationships with relatives.

As in all care, respect for the patient’s autonomy is central in palliative care. To the extent possible, the patient should be given the opportunity to participate in the medical decision-making and receive information that corresponds to the patient’s knowledge and wishes for information. This means that if a patient does not wish information about their health condition and future prospects, this should also be respected. How do palliative care professionals handle such a situation, where a patient does not want to know?

The question is investigated in an interview study by Joar Björk, who is a clinical ethicist and physician in palliative home care. He conducted six focus group interviews with staff in palliative care in Sweden, a total of 33 participants. Each interview began with an outline of an ethically challenging patient case. A man with disseminated prostate cancer is treated by a palliative care team. He has previously reiterated that it is important for him to gain complete knowledge of the illness and how his death may look. Because the team had to deal with many physical symptoms, they have not yet had time to answer his questions. When they finally get time to talk to him, he suddenly says that he does not want more information and that the issue should not be raised again. He gives no reason for his changed position, but nothing else seems to have changed and he seems to be in his right mind.

What did the interviewees say about the made-up case? The initial reaction was that it goes without saying that the patient has the right not to be informed. If a patient does not want information, then you must not impose the information on him, but must “meet the patient where he is.” But the interviewees still began to wonder about the context. Why did the man suddenly change his mind? Although the case description states that the man is competent to make decisions, this began to be doubted. Or could someone close to him have influenced him? What at first seemed obvious later appeared to be problematic.

The interviewees emphasized that in a case like this one must dig deeper and investigate whether it is really true that the patient does not want to be informed. Maybe he said that he does not want to know to appear brave, or to protect loved ones from disappointing information? Preferences can also change over time. Suddenly you do not want what you just wanted, or thought you wanted. Palliative care is a process, it was emphasized in the interviews. Thanks to the fact that the care team has continuous contact with the patient, it was felt that one could carefully probe what he really wants at regular intervals.

Other values were also at stake for the interviewees, which could further contribute to undermining what at first seemed obvious. For example, that the patient has the right to a dignified, peaceful and good death. If he is uninformed that he has a very short time left to live, he cannot prepare for death, say goodbye to loved ones, or finish certain practical tasks. It may also be more difficult to plan and provide good care to an uninformed patient, and it may feel dishonest to know something important but not tell the person concerned. The interviewees also considered the consequences for relatives of the patient’s reluctance to be informed.

The main result of the study is that the care teams found it difficult to handle a situation where a patient suddenly changes his mind and does not want to be informed. Should they not have experienced these difficulties? Should they accept what at first seemed self-evident in principle, namely that the patient has the right not to know? The interviewees themselves emphasized that care is a process, a gradually unfolding relationship, and that it is important to be flexible and continuously probe the changing will of the patient. Perhaps, after all, it is not so difficult to deal with the case in practice, even if it is not as simple as it first appeared?

The interviewees seemed unhappy about the patient’s decision, but at the same time seemed to feel that there were ways forward and that time worked in their favor. In the end, the patient probably wants to know, after all, they seemed to think. Should they not have had such an attitude towards the patient’s decision?

Read the author’s interesting discussion of the study results here: “It is very hard to just accept this” – a qualitative study of palliative care teams’ ethical reasoning when patients do not want information.

Pär Segerdahl

Written by…

Pär Segerdahl, Associate Professor at the Centre for Research Ethics & Bioethics and editor of the Ethics Blog.

Björk, J. “It is very hard to just accept this” – a qualitative study of palliative care teams’ ethical reasoning when patients do not want information. BMC Palliative Care 23, 91 (2024). https://doi.org/10.1186/s12904-024-01412-8

This post in Swedish

We like real-life ethics

Trapped in a system

Suppose a philosopher builds a system of ideas based on our mortality. It is the risk of dying, the vulnerability of all things in life, that allows us to find our lives meaningful and our life projects engaging. If we did not believe in the risk of dying and the vulnerability of all things in life, we would not care about anything at all. Therefore, we must believe what the system requires, in order to live meaningfully and be caring. In fact, everyone already believes what the system requires, argues the philosopher, even those who question it. They do it in practice, because they live committed and caring lives. This would be impossible if they did not believe what the system requires.

However, our mortality is more than a risk. It is a fact: we will die. Death is not just a possibility, something that can happen, a defeat we risk in our projects. What happens when we see the reality of death, instead of being trapped in the system’s doctrines about necessary conditions for the possibility of meaningful and committed lives? We can, of course, close our eyes and refuse to think more about it. However, we can also start thinking like never before. If I am going to die, I have to understand life before I die! I have to investigate! I have to reach clarity while I live!

In this examination of the starting point of the system, a freer thinking comes to life, which wonders rather than issues demands. What is it to live? Who am I, who say that I have a life? How did “I” and “my life” meet? Are we separate? Are we a unity? Is life limited by birth and death? Or is life extended, including the alternations between birth and death? What is life really? The small, which is limited by birth and death, or the large, which includes the alternations between birth and death? Or both at the same time? These are perhaps the first preliminary questions…

The mortality on which the system is based raises passionate questions about the concepts with which the system operates as if they had been carved in stone for eternity. It gives birth to a self-questioning life, which does not allow itself to be subdued by the system’s doctrines about what we must believe. Even the system itself is questioned, because the passion that animates the questioning is as great as the system would like to be.

However, if the questioning cares passionately about life, if mortality and vulnerability are part of the commitment – does the system thereby get in the last word?

(This post is inspired by Martin Hägglund’s book, This Life, which I recommend as a great stumbling stone for our time.)

Pär Segerdahl

Written by…

Pär Segerdahl, Associate Professor at the Centre for Research Ethics & Bioethics and editor of the Ethics Blog.

This post in Swedish

We like challenging questions

Transhumanism purifies human misery

Pär SegerdahlThe human is a miserable being. Although we are pleased about the new and better-paid job, we soon acquire more costly habits, richer friends, and madder professional duties. We are back to square one, dissatisfied with life and uncomfortable with ourselves. Why can life never be perfect?

Discontent makes us want to escape to better futures. We want to run away from worries, from boredom, from disease, from aging, from all the limitations of life, preferably even from death. We always rush to what we imagine will be a better place. As often as we find ourselves back to square one.

The eternal return of discontent thus characterizes the human condition. We imagine that everything will be perfect, if only we could escape from the present situation, which we believe limits us and causes our discontent. The result is an endless stream of whims, which again make us feel imprisoned.

Always this square one.

Transhumanism is an intellectual revivalist movement that promises that AT LAST everything will be perfect. How? Through escaping from the human herself, from this deficient creature, trapped in a biological body that is limited by disease, aging and death.

How can we escape from all human limitations? By having new technology renew us, making us perfect, no longer suffering from any of the biological limitations of life. A brave new limitless cyborg.

Who buys the salvation doctrine? Literally some of the richest technology entrepreneurs in the world. They have already pushed the boundaries as far as possible. They have tried all the escape routes, but the feeling of limitation always returns. They see no other way out than escaping from EVERYTHING. They invest in space technology to escape the planet. They invest in artificial intelligence and in the deep-freezing of their bodies, to escape the body in the future, into supercomputers that AT LAST will save them from ALL life’s limitations, including disease, aging and death.

Do you recognize the pattern? Transhumanism is human misery. Transhumanism is the escapism that always leads back to square one. It is the dream of a high-tech quantum leap from dissatisfaction. What does paradise look like? Like a high-tech return to square one.

We need new technology to solve problems in the world. When coupled with human discontent, however, technology reinforces the pattern. Only you can free yourself from the pattern. By no longer escaping to an ideal future. It does not work. Running to the future is the pattern of your misery.

Transhumanism is the intellectual purification of human misery, not the way out of it.

Pär Segerdahl

This post in Swedish

We challenge habits of thought : the Ethics Blog

The debate about after-birth abortion continues

Last year the Journal of Medical Ethics published an article by two philosophers claiming that the same arguments that support abortion also support abortion of newborns.

The article provoked strong reactions and I too felt I had to comment on the article here on The Ethics Blog.

What’s so provocative? I’m not so sure it is the conclusion that if we allow abortion we also should allow abortion of newborns. The two philosophers actually never concluded with any practical recommendations. They only wanted to theoretically explore the logic in the arguments for abortion.

And maybe this is what’s so provocative, or rather tragi-comical: the spirit in which one approaches questions of life and death as an entrepreneur might use the annual report to consider his reasons for terminating a project that can become a burden for the company.

Recently, the same journal reissued the article; this time with two editorials and a number of comments by ethicists (here).

The reissuing of the article reaffirms the attitude that the burning hot questions of life and death should be discussed as a rational entrepreneur manages his firm.

Should we allow infanticide? We’ll have to postpone decision until we’ve received the annual report from the neuroscientists on neonates’ capacity for thought.

Pär Segerdahl

We follow debates : The Ethics Blog